Marketing and the Vulnerable
Download
Report
Transcript Marketing and the Vulnerable
Philosophy 223
Marketing
Advertising, Information and Vulnerability
Moral Dimensions of Marketing
The aim of all marketing strategies or techniques is the sale.
Producing and pricing goods is an important element of this,
but advertising and product placement are the means by
which the sale is promoted.
We often assume that these aspects of marketing are a
relatively benign aspect of contemporary business. After all,
they involve no violation of employee rights or
responsibilities, and no obvious abdication of corporate
responsibility.
Furthermore, advertisement is directed at free individuals
who are not externally coerced to accept the claims made by
the advertisers. Despite these facts, there are significant
ethical issues that arise in these contexts.
A Question of Influence
The aim of marketing and product
placement is to influence the purchasing
decision of the consumer.
Common moral opinion suggests that there
are ethically acceptable and unacceptable
means of influencing consumer behavior.
Acceptable means include persuading, asking, informing
and advising.
Unacceptable ways include threats, coercion, deception
and lying.
Influence and Manipulation
The unacceptable means of influencing people
share a common feature: they all aim at
manipulating the consumer.
Manipulation seeks to guide behavior without
the consent or awareness of the target.
Manipulation is not control; it’s more subtle.
The better you understand how people think, the more
effectively you can manipulate them.
Manipulation should be contrasted with forms of rational
influence like persuasion.
Manipulative Marketing
It should be easy to see that critics of
advertising and product placement
techniques focus on instances where
the intent of the techniques is clearly
manipulative.
Another area of concern is marketing
research, in particular research aimed
at consumer psychology.
Is There Anything Wrong with
Manipulation?
Before we examine some of the particular concerns
raised by ethicists and business people, we should
answer this question.
All of the general ethical approaches we’ve examined
raise important objections to many forms of
manipulation.
Manipulation is characterized by a failure to treat others with
respect by treating them as a means rather than an end.
Manipulation thus tends to decrease overall utility by making
social interaction more difficult.
Manipulation conflicts with many of the most commonly
articulated virtues (ex. honesty).
Deceptive and Unfair Marketing
Some marketing techniques are obviously
unethical.
Prominent among these are techniques that
seek to deceive consumers or seek an unfair
advantage over competitors.
Is the “Sales at World Camera and
Electronics” case (336) an example of
deceptive or unfair marketing.
Deception and Manipulation in
Advertising
Given the harms that arise from deceptive and
unfair advertising, society has good reasons to
target these forms of advertising.
The focus on intent seems promising. Perhaps we
could target advertising that intends to deceive.
However, intent is difficult to discern, so some
have argued that we should focus on effects.
In both cases, it seems necessary to agree on some
definition of the qualities of a “reasonable
consumer.”
Galbraith and the Dependence Effect
Economist John Kenneth Galbraith argued that contrary to
common assumptions, advertisement doesn’t just respond to
demand, it in large measure creates it. Galbraith labeled this
capacity the “Dependence Effect.”
Galbraith went on to argue that there are three negative
consequences of the DE:
It reverses the law of supply and demand, making demand
a function of supply.
It creates and encourages irrational consumer desires,
which limit the efficiency of markets.
Advertising that creates demands undercuts consumer
autonomy.
Some Implications of the Dependence
Effect
If Galbraith’s concerns are legitimate, there are a
number of important consequences.
Undercutting consumer autonomy would violate traditional
ethical standards.
Market exchanges which appear to increase overall
satisfaction would actually not do so.
The reversal of the law of supply and demand significantly
undercuts the democratic nature of markets and makes it
difficult to justify the accumulation of wealth by a few
individuals on the ground of their supposed responsiveness
to consumer demand.
The Dependence Effect and Autonomy
The thin wedge of this issue is the question of
autonomy.
Is it the case that common forms of advertising
undercut consumer autonomy?
Answering this question requires a distinction
prepared for in our analysis of manipulation.
We saw there that undercutting autonomy does not require
actually controlling a person.
That is, a person can act without constraint, but still not
be acting autonomously.
Autonomous Behavior vs. Autonomous
Desire
We can account for the gap between action and
autonomy, by noting a difference between
autonomous behavior and autonomous desires.
If I act without constraint, I can in one sense be
said to be behaving autonomously.
However, if the desires upon which I act are not
autonomously chosen, then the lack of constraint
does not guarantee autonomy.
Is the drug addict acting autonomously when they, without
external interference, use drugs?
A Framework for Understanding Desire
A way of understanding the apparent conflict lived by
an addict it to draw a distinction between first-order
and second-order desires.
A first-order desire is any desire I have at the moment.
A second-order desire is one I have on the basis of a
reflective consideration of my interests.
Autonomy requires this capacity for reflection.
It is thus the capacity to form and act in accordance
with second-order desires which makes a person
autonomous.
Autonomy and the Addict
The addict may have strong first-order
desires for that to which they are addicted,
but any reflective individual in that
situation is going to have strong secondorder desires to be free of the addiction.
Given the analysis just offered, to the
extent that the addict acts on their firstorder desires rather than their second-order
desires, they act non-autonomously.
Autonomy and Advertising
Under what conditions are the desire-creating
capacities of advertising going to be consistent with the
autonomy of consumers?
Only in that situation where the creation of first-order desires
does not conflict with legitimate, reflectively established secondorder desires.
This is reflected in the “cooling-off” periods common in consumer
protection law.
In other words, the fact that consumers often respond
favorably to desire creating marketing techniques is no
evidence of their acceptability.
Willingly participating in “therapeutic shopping” is not enough.
The individual would have had to reflect upon the nature of such
an enterprise and determined its appropriateness.
Further Complications
Even this picture may fail to address the full
complicity of advertising in undercutting consumer
autonomy.
Persuasive advertising actively contests the development of
the critical, reflective skills necessary for the formation of
autonomous second-order desires.
The sheer volume of advertising which bombards us
everyday renders even the most critical and reflective
individuals incapable of immunizing themselves from
autonomy-limiting first-order desire creation.
Arrington, “Advertising and Behavior
Control”
This article considers whether or not a
common technique of advertising, puffery,
illegitimately interferes with consumer
autonomy via manipulation.
The author argues that generally it does
not.
His argument rests on analysis of the
concepts of desire, free choice, and
manipulation.
Puffery
Puffery is the practice of a seller making
exaggerated or fanciful claims about a product or
service.
Some argue that the use of puffery constitutes
manipulation.
Examples: “Better ingredients, better pizza.”
Axe Body Spray
Arrington on Autonomy and Desire
Autonomous Desire
We act autonomously when we act in a manner
consistent with our second-order desires.
Autonomous Desire and Choice
Based on knowledge of information relevant to
choice. Desire is only autonomous when it’s
rational (ensures consistency).
Free Choice (Acting Freely)
We act freely when we do things for a reason.
What about Manipulation?
As Arrington understands it,
manipulation involves:
Intention
Causality
Guaranteed Control of Outcome
Arrington’s Conclusion
Arrington argues that persuasive advertising
typically does not undermine autonomy.
Consumers typically
Consumers typically
be good ones.
Consumers typically
desires.
Consumers typically
act freely (on reasons).
act on reasons they take to
act on their second-order
are not manipulated.
Holley, “Information Disclosure in Sales”
This essay defends a rule or principle of disclosure for
ethical sales.
How much information are sales people ethically
required to disclose? Five levels of disclosure:
Minimal Information: buyer is solely responsible;
Modified Minimal Information: disclose only what is necessary
to avoid risk;
Fairness Rule: safety information plus unavailable
information;
Mutual Benefit Rule: safety information plus information
needed for a reasonable judgment;
Maximal Information Rule: all relevant information.
What’s Required?
Holley first considers if it would be appropriate to merely
consider the interests of the consumer. What rule would you
want if you were the consumer (the Golden Rule)?
Holley thinks that this focus ignores the appropriate advocacy of the
salesperson.
This leads him to consider the two versions of the minimal
information rule, but this seems to ignore legitimate interests of
consumers.
Addressing the various ways in which consumers are
informationally vulnerable leads him to reject the fairness rule.
He thus concludes that the mutual benefit rule is best, as it
allows for product advocacy but protects consumer interests.
Nature and Types of Vulnerability
• Vulnerability refers to a susceptibility to harm; more
specifically it refers to factors that individuals possess
that makes them more susceptible than their fellows.
• Individuals exhibit General Vulnerability when a
physical or psychological feature they exhibit makes
them susceptible to some harm.
•
Elderly, addicts.
• Individuals exhibit Consumer Vulnerability to the
extent that their ability to participate in rational
exchanges is impaired.
•
Children
Marketing to Vulnerability
• Marketing techniques can target general
vulnerabilities or consumer vulnerabilities.
• Clearly techniques that target consumer
vulnerabilities are illegitimate, on the grounds of
our analysis of autonomy.
• Just as clearly, many general vulnerabilities make
individuals vulnerable as consumers.
• Elderly, infirm are vulnerable to ads that play on their anxieties.
Low income people vulnerable to high priced consumer goods.
Brenkert, “Marketing and the
Vulnerable”
This essay defends the view that some consumers lack
“market competency” and that such vulnerable
individuals should not be targeted by marketers in ways
that take advantage of their vulnerability.
Basically, market competency refers to the knowledge
and context appropriate to a reasonable consumer,
which includes:
The ability to determine differences in quality and optimal
pricing.
Knowledge of legal rights.
Knowledge of the products and their characteristics.
Possession of appropriate resources.
An Account of Vulnerability
Vulnerable individuals operate with conditions or
incapacities that impede their ability as normal
market participants.
Physical vulnerabilities
Cognitive vulnerabilities
These vulnerabilities are magnified when we think
about their implications.
Less able to protect their interests
Possess these vulnerabilities due to factors beyond their control
Often unaware of their vulnerabilities
Vulnerabilities render them susceptible to harm
Justified Market Relations
Morally justified market relations require:
that all participants be capable of exhibiting market
competency;
that the markets are characterized by free competition;
the competition is open;
deception and fraud are not used.
On this basis, we can conclude that it is not
morally acceptable to market goods to especially
vulnerable people with the intention of taking
advantage of their vulnerability.
Individuals who are simply lazy (do not do their homework)
should not count as vulnerable.
Elliot, “The Drug Pushers”
The context of Elliot’s article is the
potential conflict between the duties of
doctors to their patients and the goals of
pharmaceutical reps (to get doctors to
prescribe their companies’ medications).
Though not necessarily conflicting, the
different foci of these two parties can
present significant moral concerns.
Gene Carbona
As the anecdotes of Mr. Carbona, supported
by other participants in the industry and
studies in the medical literature,
demonstrate, the persuasive efforts of drug
reps have a significant impact on drug sales.
In and of itself, this should pose few
concerns. However, when the drugs in
question are of little benefit, or even pose
possible risks to patients, concerns are
legitimate.
Should we be concerned?
Consider the following, all gleaned from
Elliot’s article:
In 1997, the average ROI on a dollar spent on drug repping
was $10.29 (twice that on print advertising to physicians
and 7 times on print advertising to consumers).
The pharmaceutical industries lobbying organization is the
largest in the country.
9 out of 10 medical students have been asked or required
to attend a pharmaceutical industry sales event.
The pharmaceutical industry provides ~90% of the annual
monies spent on continuing education for doctors.
Two General Concerns
First, referring back to our initial considerations,
we should probably wonder about the autonomy of
doctors influenced by reps.
Particularly in connection two the relationship between
first and second order desires.
Secondly, there are a number of vulnerabilities to
be concerned about: patients, doctors and their
staffs, and even, as Elliot suggests at the end of his
article, the reps themselves.