Transcript Player 2

Doctoral Program and Advanced Degree in Sustainable Energy Systems
Doctoral Program in Mechanical Engineering
Ecological Economics
Week 2
Tiago Domingos
Assistant Professor
Environment and Energy Section
Department of Mechanical Engineering
Preferences
• Notation
– Strictly preferred: ( x1 , x2 )  ( y1 , y2 )
– Indifferent: ( x1 , x2 ) ~ ( y1 , y2 )
– Weakly preferred: ( x1 , x2 )( y1 , y2 )
• Assumptions about preferences
– Complete: we assume that any two bundles can be compared.
That is, given any x-bundle and any y-bundle, we assume that
x1, x2    y1, y2  , or  y1 , y2   x1 , x2 , or both, in which
case the consumer is indifferent between the two bundles. Or
in mathematics, a binary relation R over a set X is total if it
holds for all a and b in X that a is related to b or b is related to
a (or both). a, b  X , aRb  bRa
Violation: extreme situations involving life or death choices where
ranking the alternatives might be difficult or even impossible
Preferences
• Assumptions about preferences
– Reflexive: we assume that any bundle is at least as good as
itself: x1 , x2   x1 , x2  . A reflexive relation R on set X is one
where for all a in X, a is R-related to itself. a  X , aRa
Violation: Endowment effect
The value of a good increases when it becomes part of a
persons endowment.
Value of a good A = ai
Purchase of good A
Value of good A = af > ai
Loss
aversion
Preferences
• The marginal benefit for the first glass of water is
higher than the same amount of diamonds… but the
price of diamonds is higher…
– Use value: in our daily live, the first glass of water is more
important than the diamonds
– Exchange value: the price of diamonds is much higher than
the price of water (the same amont) because of scarcity
– Surplus : difference between use value and exchange value
Preferences
• Assumptions about preferences
– Transitive: if x1 , x2    y1 , y2  and  y1 , y2   z1 , z2  , then we
assume that x1 , x2   z1 , z2  . In other words, if the consumer
thinks that bundle X is at least as good as Y and that Y is at
least as good as Z, then the consumer thinks that X is at least
as good as Z
Violation: Rugby Players
A player is chosen over other if two of his characteristics are better
Weight
Velocity
Discipline
Player 1
150
Low
Average
Player 2
120
High
Low
Player 3
100
Average
High
Player 1 preferred to Player 2, Player 2 preferred to Player 3
but Player 3 preferred to Player 1
Preferences
Strictly
preferred
Indifferent
Weakly
preferred
Complete



Reflexive



Transitive



Preferences
• Indifference versus incomplete
– Consider that I am indifferent to basket players, if they have
the same height. If I consider only those kind of players, then
the relation is always complete. If I consider all the players,
including those who have different height, then the relation is
not complete because I cannot chose between two players
with different height.
– Being indifferent is not being incomplete. The fact that the
bundle oranges is indifferent to the bundle bananas, does not
mean that I cannot chose.
Preferences
• Assumptions about preferences
– Monotonic: we assume that more is better, that is, that we are
talking about goods, not bads. More precisely, if x1 , x2  is a
bundle of goods and  y1 , y2  is a bundle of goods with at least
as much of both goods and more of one, then  y1 , y2   x1 , x2 
– Convex: we assume that averages are preferred to extremes.
That is, if we take two bundles of goods x1 , x2  and  y1 , y2 
on the same indifference curve and take a weighted average
of the two bundles such as tx1  1  t x2 , ty1  1  t y2 , 0  t  1
then the average bundle will be at least as good as or strictly
preferred to each of the two extreme bundles. (Example:
olives and icecream)
Preferences
• Indiference curves
– Graph the set of bundles that are indifferent to some bundle.
 y1 , y2 
– Indifference curves are like contour lines on a map.
– Note that indifference curves describing two distinct levels of
preferences cannot cross
Preferences
• Perfect Substitutes
Preferences
• Perfect Complements
Preferences
• Bads
Preferences
• Neutral
Preferences
• Satiation
Preferences
• Marginal rate of substitution
x2
x1
MRS
Utility
• Interpreting
– Summarizes preferences
– A utility function assigns a number to each bundle of goods
so that more preferred bundles get higher numbers
– that is, u(x1, x2) > u(y1, y2) if and only if (x1, x2) ≻ (y1, y2)
– only the ordering of bundles counts, so this is a theory of
ordinal utility
• Ordinal vs Cardinal utility
– The size of the utility difference between two bundles of
goods is suposed to have some sort of significance.
Bundle
U1
U2
U3
A
3
17
-1
B
2
10
-2
C
1
0.002
-3
Utility
• Marginal utility (may be called “oportunity cost”)
MU 1 
U
U
; MU 2 
x1
x2
MRS  
MU 1
MU 2
See Varian, Chapter
4 – APPENDIX
Utility
• Cobb-Douglas preferences
u x1 , x2   x1c x2d and x1 , x2 , c, d  0
ln u x1 , x2   c ln x1   d ln x2 
See Varian, Chapter
4 – EXAMPLE:
Cobb-Douglas
Preferences
Choice
• Geometric solution
Choice
• Analytical solution
– Problem formulation:
max U x1 , x2 
s.t. p1 x1  p2 x2  m and x1 , x2  0
– It can be solved using Lagrange multipliers:
x1 , x2 ,    U  x1 , x2     p1 x1  p2 x2  m 

 
 x  0
 1
MU 1  p1  0
 MU 1 MU 2

 


p2
 0  MU 2  p2  0   p1

 x2
p x  p x  m
p x  p x  m
2 2
 1 1
1 1
2 2

 
 0
 
Gives the convertion between money and utility
Choice
• Analytical solution
– It must be noticed that x1  0  x2  0  p1  0  p2  0
– If the Lagrangian solution does not respect it, we have a
corner solution given by:
x1  0  x2 
m
p2
x2  0  x1 
m
p1
Choice
• Example: Cobb-Douglas Demand Functions
ux1, x2   x1c x2d
– Monotonic tranformation:
ln u x1, x2   c ln x1  d ln x2
– The problem:
max c ln x1  d ln x2
x1 , x2
such that p1 x1  p2 x2  m
– The solution:
c

x

 cx2 p1
 1 cd



dx
p

 1

2
p x  p x  m
x  d
2 2
 1 1
 2 c  d
m
p1
m
p2
Demand
Effect on demand of a good
Change in income
Quantity demanded increases with income– normal goods.
For some normal goods, the quantity demanded increases
more than proportionally with income – luxury goods. For
other normal goods, the quantity demanded increases less
than proportionally with income – necessary goods.
Quantity demanded decreases with an increase in income –
inferior good (example: low quality food)
Change in own price
The quantity demanded for good 1 increases when its price
decreases – ordinary good
The quantity demanded for good 1 decreases with its price
– Giffen good
Change in the price
of the other good
The demand for good 1 increases when the price of good
2 increases – good 1 is a substitute for good 2
The demand for good 1 decreases when the price of good 2
increases – good 1 is a complement to good 2
Assignments
• Exercise 4 from Preferences
• Exercise 2 from Choice
• and the following exercise
(2nd Season Exam of 2004-05). Joana likes chocolate cake and icecream, but after eating 10 slices of cake, she is full of it, and eating more
chocolate cake leaves her less satisfied. Joana always prefers to eat more
ice-cream than less. Joana’s parents allow her to leave aside everything
she dislikes eating. Sketch indifference curves that are consistent with
this description.