The Power of Quantum Advice

Download Report

Transcript The Power of Quantum Advice

A Theory of Isolatability
Scott Aaronson Andrew Drucker
MIT
Freeze-Dried Computation
Motivating Question: How much useful computational work
can one “store” in (say) an n-qubit quantum state, or a coin
whose bias is an arbitrary real number?
Potentially a huge amount!
We give a new tool—called “isolatability”—for ruling out the
possibility of such extravagant encodings.
Idea: Take some advice resource (such as a coin or a quantum
state), and simulate it using a short classical string, together
with a polynomial number of untrusted advice resources.
In other words, all the relevant information in the advice
resource gets packed into an ordinary string (which we say
“isolates” the resource), and we're left with just a
computational search problem—of finding coins, quantum
states, etc. that are consistent with the string.
Part I: The Majority-Certificates Lemma
Our basic tool
Part II: Application to Quantum Advice
BQP/qpoly  QMA/poly
Part III: Application to Advice Coins
PSPACE/coin  PSPACE/poly
Part I: The MajorityCertificates Lemma
Intuition: We’re given a black box
x
f
f(x)
that computes some Boolean function f:{0,1}n{0,1} belonging
to a “small” set S (meaning, of size 2poly(n)). Someone wants to
prove to us that f equals (say) the all-0 function, by having us
check a polynomial number of outputs f(x1),…,f(xm).
This is trivially impossible!
But what if we get 3 black
boxes, and are allowed to
simulate f=f0 by taking the
point-wise MAJORITY of
their outputs?
f0
f1
f2
f3
f4
f5
x1
0
1
0
0
0
0
x2
0
0
1
0
0
0
x3
0
0
0
1
0
0
x4
0
0
0
0
1
0
x5
0
0
0
0
0
1
Majority-Certificates Lemma
Definitions: A certificate is a partial Boolean function
C:{0,1}n{0,1,*}. A Boolean function f:{0,1}n{0,1} is
consistent with C, if f(x)=C(x) whenever C(x){0,1}. The size of
C is the number of inputs x such that C(x){0,1}.
Lemma: Let S be a set of Boolean functions f:{0,1}n{0,1}, and
let f*S. Then there exist m=O(n) certificates C1,…,Cm, each of
size O(log|S|), such that
(i) Some fiS is consistent with each Ci, and
(ii) If f1S is consistent with C1, f2S is consistent with C2, and
so on, then MAJ(f1,…,fm)=f*, where MAJ denotes pointwise
majority.
Proof Idea
By symmetry, we can assume f* is the all-0 function. Consider a
two-player, zero-sum matrix game:
Bob picks an input x{0,1}n
The lemma follows from this claim! Just choose
certificates C1,…,Cm independently from Alice’s winning
Alice picks
a certificate
distribution.
Then by a Chernoff bound, almost certainly
C ofMAJ(f
size k1(x),…,f
consistent
m(x))=0 for all f1,…,fm consistent with C1,…,Cm
with someand
fSall inputs x{0,1}n. So clearly there exist
respectively
C1,…,Cm with this property.
Alice wins this game if f(x)=0 for all fS consistent with C.
Crucial Claim: Alice has a mixed strategy that lets her win
>90% of the time.
Proof of Claim
Use the Minimax Theorem! Given a distribution D over x, it’s
enough to create a fixed certificate C such that
1
Pr f consistent with C s.t. f x   1  .
xD
10
Stage I: Choose x1,…,xt independently from D, for some
t=O(log|S|). Then with high probability, requiring
f(x1)=…=f(xt)=0 kills off every fS such that
1
Pr  f  x   1  .
xD
10
Stage II: Repeatedly add a constraint f(xi)=bi that kills at least
half the remaining functions. After ≤ log2|S| iterations, we’ll
have winnowed S down to just a single function fS.
Part II: Application to
Quantum Advice
BQP/qpoly is the class of problems solvable in quantum
polynomial time, with the help of polynomial-size “quantum
advice states”
Formally: a language L is in BQP/qpoly if there exists a polynomial
time quantum algorithm A, as well as quantum advice states {|n}n
on poly(n) qubits, such that for every input x of size n, A(x,|n)
decides whether or not xL with error probability at most 1/3
YQP (“Yoda Quantum Polynomial-Time”) is the
same, except we also require that for every alleged
advice state , A(x,) outputs either the right
answer or “FAIL” with probability at least 2/3
BQP  YQP  QMA  BQP/qpoly
QUANTUM ADVICE IS POWERFUL
Watrous 2000: For any fixed, finite black-box group Gn and
subgroup Hn≤Gn, deciding membership in Hn is in BQP/qpoly
The quantum advice state is just an equal superposition |Hn over
the elements of Hn
We don’t know how to solve the same problem in BQP/poly
A.-Kuperberg 2007: There exists a “quantum oracle”
separating BQP/qpoly from BQP/poly
NO IT ISN’T
A. 2004: BQP/qpoly  PP/poly = PostBQP/poly
Quantum advice can be simulated by classical advice, combined with
postselection on unlikely measurement outcomes
A. 2006: HeurBQP/qpoly = HeurYQP/poly
Trusted quantum advice can be simulated on most inputs by trusted
classical advice combined with untrusted quantum advice
New Result: BQP/qpoly = YQP/poly
Trusted quantum advice is equivalent in power to trusted
classical advice combined with untrusted quantum advice.
(“Quantum states never need to be trusted”)
“PHYSICS” IMPLICATION
Let ρ be any quantum state on n qubits. Then for all m,ε, there
exists a 2-local Hamiltonian H=H1+⋯+HL on poly(n,m,1/ε)
qubits, such that any ground state |φ of H can be used to
simulate ρ (with error ε) on all quantum circuits of size at most
m. In other words, there exists an efficient mapping C→C′ such
that for all circuits C of size m,
PrC '    accepts   PrC   accepts    .
What Does It Mean?
Preparing quantum advice states is no harder than preparing
ground states of local Hamiltonians
This explains a once-mysterious relationship between
quantum proofs and quantum advice: efficient
preparability of ground states would imply both
QMA=QCMA and BQP/qpoly=BQP/poly
“Quantum Karp-Lipton Theorem”: NP-complete problems are
not efficiently solvable using quantum advice, unless some
uniform complexity classes collapse unexpectedly
QCMA/qpoly  QMA/poly: classical proofs and quantum advice
can be simulated with quantum proofs and classical advice
PSPACE/poly
A.’06
QMA/qpoly
PP/poly
QMA/poly
This work
PP
QCMA/qpoly
BQP/qpoly
=YQP/poly
QCMA/poly
QMA
BQP/poly
YQP
QCMA
BQP
Minimax
Theorem
Safe
Winnowing
Lemma
Circuit Learning
(Bshouty et al.)
Real MajorityCertificates Lemma
LOCAL HAMILTONIANS is
QMA-complete
(Kitaev)
Covering Lemma
(Alon et al.)
Learning of pConcept Classes
(Bartlett & Long)
MajorityCertificates
Lemma
Cook-Levin Theorem
Holevo’s Theorem
Random Access
Code Lower Bound
(Ambainis et al.)
Fat-Shattering Bound
(A.’06)
QMA=QMA+
(Aharonov & Regev)
HeurBQP/qpoly=HeurYQP/poly
(A.’06)
BQP/qpoly=YQP/poly
Quantum advice no harder
than ground state preparation
Used as lemma
Generalizes
“Lifting” the Majority-Certificates Lemma
Boolean Majority-Certificates
BQP/qpoly=YQP/poly Proof
Set S of Boolean functions
Set S of p(n)-qubit mixed states
“True” function f*S
“True” advice state |n
Other functions f1,…,fm
Other states 1,…,m
Certificate Ci to isolate fi
Measurement Ei to isolate I
New Difficulty
Solution
The class of p(n)-qubit quantum states is
Result of A.’06 on learnability of quantum
infinitely large! And even if we discretize it, it’s states (building on Ambainis et al. 1999)
still doubly-exponentially large
Instead of Boolean functions f:{0,1}n{0,1},
now we have real functions f:{0,1}n[0,1]
representing the expectation values
Learning theory has tools to deal with
this: fat-shattering dimension, -covers…
(Alon et al. 1997)
How do we verify a quantum witness without
destroying it?
QMA=QMA+ (Aharonov & Regev 2003)
What if a certificate asks us to verify Tr(E)≤a,
but Tr(E) is “right at the knife-edge”?
“Safe Winnowing Lemma”
Majority-Certificates Lemma, Real Case
Lemma: Let S be a set of functions f:{0,1}ⁿ→[0,1], let f∗∈S, and
let ε>0. Then we can find m=O(n/ε²) functions f1,…,fm∈S, sets
X1,…,Xm⊆{0,1}ⁿ each of size
 n

k  O 3 fat / 48 S ,


and


2

  
 n fat / 48 S  
for which the following holds. All functions g1,…,gm∈S that
satisfy max gi x   f i x    for all i[m] also satisfy
xX i
maxn g x   f * x    ,
x0,1
where
1
g x  : g1 x     g m x .
m
Theorem: BQP/qpoly = YQP/poly.
Proof Sketch: YQP/poly  BQP/qpoly is immediate. For the
other direction, let LBQP/qpoly. Let M be a quantum
algorithm that decides L using advice state |n. Define
f  x : PrM x,   accepts
Let S = {f : }. Then S has “fat-shattering dimension” at most
poly(n), by A.’06. So we can apply the real version of the
Majority-Certificates Lemma to S. This yields certificates
C1,…,Cm (for some m=poly(n)), such that any states 1,…,m
consistent with C1,…,Cm respectively satisfy


1
f 1 x     f  m x   f  n
m
n
x   
for all x{0,1}n (regardless of entanglement). To check the Ci’s,
we use the “QMA+ super-verifier” of Aharonov & Regev.
Quantum Karp-Lipton Theorem
Karp-Lipton 1982: If NP  P/poly, then coNPNP = NPNP.
Our quantum analogue:
If NP  BQP/qpoly, then coNPNP  QMAPromiseQMA.
Proof Idea: A coNPNP statement has the form x y R(x,y).
By the hypothesis and BQP/qpoly = YQP/poly, there exists an
advice string s, such that any quantum state  consistent with s
lets us solve NP problems (and some such  is consistent).
In QMAPromiseQMA, first guess an s that’s consistent with some
state . Then use the oracle to search for an x and  such that,
if  is consistent with s, then R(x,Q(x,)) holds, where Q is a
quantum algorithm that searches for a y such that R(x,y).
Part III: Application to
Advice Coins
Erik Demaine (motivated by a
computational genetics problem):
“Suppose a PSPACE machine can flip a
coin with Bernoulli probability p an
unlimited number of times. Can it
extract an exponential amount of
information (or even more) about p?”
Me: “I’m sure whatever the answer is, it’s
obvious...”
Didn’t seem too likely there could be
superpowerful “Advice Coins”
Indeed, Hellman & Cover proved the
following in 1970...
Suppose a finite automaton M is trying to decide
whether a coin has p=½ or p=½+. Then even if it can
flip the coin an unlimited number of times, M needs
(1/) states to succeed with probability (say) 2/3.
This result seems to imply PSPACE/coinPSPACE/poly,
since we could take the first poly(n) bits of p as the
advice. But it breaks down if p is close to 0 or 1!
Furthermore, quantum mechanics
nullifies the Hellman-Cover Theorem!
Theorem: For any >0, it’s possible to distinguish a coin
with p=½ from a coin with p=½+ using a single qubit of
memory, with error probability independent of .
Halt with probability
time
step the coin.
1 ~2/100 at each
Keep
flipping
0 1
Expected difference in final 2angle after
halting,
in coin
p=½
Whenever
the
vs. p=½+ cases: 1 radian
lands heads, rotate
Standard deviation in angle:
/100 radians
0 counterclockwise.
Whenever it lands tails,
rotate /100 radians
clockwise.
Theorem: Despite these obstacles,
BQPSPACE/coin = PSPACE/coin = PSPACE/poly.
Proof: Suffices to show BQPSPACE/coin  PSPACE/poly.
Let 0 = quantum operation applied to our memory
qubits whenever coin lands heads,
1 = operation applied when it lands tails
Then induced operation at each time step:
We’re interested in a fixed-point of p: a mixed state p
such that
Fixed-Points of Superoperators
Already studied by [A.-Watrous 2008],
in the context of quantum computing
with closed timelike curves
Our result there: BQPCTC = PCTC = PSPACE
Quantum computers with CTCs have exactly the same
power as classical computers with CTCs, namely PSPACE
(or: “CTCs make time and space equivalent as
computational resources”)
Key Lemma: Let a(p) be the probability that an S-state
quantum finite automaton accepts, if each input bit is 1
with independent probability p. Then a(p) is a degree-S2
rational function of p.
Proof Idea: We can write a(p) as
1 T
lim  Acc pt 0  Acc  Acc  p Acc .
T  T
t 1
Furthermore, each entry of p can be written as a
degree-S2 rational function of p, by using Cramer’s Rule
on S2S2 matrices.
Hence a(p) is itself a degree-S2 rational function of p,
except possibly at a finite number of singularities:
ax(p)
p
A further continuity argument rules out the singularities,
except possibly at p=0 and p=1.
Now, by calculus, a degree-S2 rational function can cross
the line y=½ at most 2S2 times…
Given a BQPSPACE/coin machine M, let ax(p) be its
acceptance probability on input x{0,1}n and a coin with
Bernoulli probability p.
Challenge: How can we describe p well enough to compute
ax(p) for every x, using only poly(n) bits?
ax(p)
p
Finishing the Argument (Sketch)
We’ve upper-bounded how many distinct Boolean
functions f:{0,1}n{0,1} can be expressed, as we vary p
from 0 to 1.
So by the Majority-Certificates Lemma, we can simulate
PSPACE/coin using a PSPACE/poly machine, combined
with poly(n) untrusted advice coins.
We then get a computational search problem: finding
coin biases p1,…,pm that are consistent with the /poly
advice string.
We can solve that problem in PSPACE, using NC
algorithms for root-finding developed by Neff and Pan
When Can An O(1)-State Finite
Automaton Detect an  Change to
the Bias of a Coin?
Open Problems
Find other applications of isolatability
Circuit complexity? Communication complexity?
Learning theory? Quantum information?
Optimality of the Majority-Certificates Lemma?
Quantum finite automata: are their limiting acceptance
probabilities continuous functions of p, for p(0,1)?
Prove a classical oracle separation between BQP/poly
and BQP/qpoly=YQP/poly
Promised Application to “Physics”
By Kitaev et al., we know LOCAL HAMILTONIANS is QMA-complete.
Furthermore, in their reduction, the witness is a “history state”
1
 :
T
T
t
t 1
t
Measuring this state yields the original QMA witness |1 with
(1/poly(n)) probability. Hence |1 can be recovered from
 poly  n 
 ' : 
So given any language LBQP/qpoly=YQP/poly, we can use the
Kitaev et al. reduction to get a local Hamiltonian H whose
unique ground state is |’. We can then use |’ to recover
the YQP witness |, and thereby decide L