Transcript A(x)
Lesson 3
Validity of arguments
Marie Duží
Logical entailment
• A formula A logically follows from a set of formulas M,
denoted M |= A, iff A is true in every model of the set M.
• Recall Definition 1. The circumstances are modelled in
accordance with the expressive power of a given logic.
• PL valuations (True – 1, False - 0) of elementary
atomic sentences
• FOL interpretations of predicate and functional
symbols
– “Under all the circumstances” means in all valuations /
interpretations that make premises true (i.e. in all models of the
premises) the conclusion must be true as well.
Logical entailment in PL
• He is at home (h) or he has gone to a pub (p)
• If he is at home (h) then he is waiting for us (w)
• If he is not waiting (w) for us then he has gone to the pub (p).
h, p, w | h p, h w | w p
1
1
1
1
0
0
0
0
1
1
0
0
1
1
0
0
1
0
1
0
1
0
1
0
1
1
1
1
1
1
0
0
1
0
1
0
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
0
1
1
1
0
conclusion
is true in all
the four models
of premises
Logical entailment in PL
• He is at home (h) or he has gone to a pub (p)
• If he is at home (h) then he is waiting for us (w)
• If he is not waiting (w) for us then he has gone to the pub (p).
h p, h w | w p
• The table has 2n lines!
Hence, an indirect proof is more effective:
• Assume that the argument is not valid. But then there must be
a valuation that satisfies all the premises but not the conclusion:
h p,
1
•
1
contradiction
0
h w | w p
1
0
10 0
1 0
0
Logical entailment in PL
• All the arguments with the same logical
form as a valid argument are valid:
h p, h w |= w p
For variables h, p, w any elementary
sentence can be substituted:
He plays a piano or studies logic.
If he plays a piano then he is a virtuous.
If he is not a virtuous then he studies logic.
Valid argument – the same valid logical form
Logical entailment
• An argument is valid, P1,...,Pn |= Z, iff
the implicative formula is a tautology:
|= (P1 ... Pn) Z.
• A proof that a formula is a tautology or that
a conclusion Z logically follows from
premises can be performed:
a) In the direct way – for instance by a truth-value
table (only in PL), by natural deduction, etc.
b) In the indirect way: P1 ... Pn Z is a
contradiction; hence the set of premises + negated
conclusion {P1, ..., Pn, Z} is contradictory, i.e., does
not have a model: there is no valuation under which
all the elements of the set are true.
A proof of a tautology
|= ((p q) q) p
Indirect:
((p q) q) p negated f., must be a contradiction
1
1 attempt whether it can be 1
1
1
1
1
0
contradiction
There is no valuation under which the negated formula is
true. Therefore, the original formula is a tautology
The most important tautologies
in PL
Tautologies with one propositional variable:
|= p p
|= p p
the law of excluded middle
|= (p p) the law of contradiction
|= p p
the law of double negation
Algebraic laws for conjunction,
disjunction and equivalence
• |= (p q) (q p)
• |= (p q) (q p)
• |= (p q) (q p)
commutative laws
• |= [(p q) r] [p (q r)]
• |= [(p q) r] [p (q r)]
• |= [(p q) r] [p (q r)]
associative laws
• |= [(p q) r] [(p r) (q r)]
• |= [(p q) r] [(p r) (q r)]
distributive laws
Laws of implication
|=
|=
|=
|=
|=
p (q p)
(p p) q
(p q) (q p)
(p (q r)) ((p q) r)
(p (q r)) (q (p r))
law of simplification
Duns Scot’s law
law of contra-position
premises joint
order of premises does not matter
|= (p q) ((q r) (p r))
|= ((p q) (q r)) (p r)
|= (p (q r)) ((p q) (p r))
hypothetic sylogism
transitivity of implication
Frege’s law
|= (p p) p
|= ((p q) (p q)) p
reductio ad absurdum
reductio ad absurdum
|= (p q) p , |= (p q) q
|= p (p q) , |= q (p q)
Laws of transformation
|=
|=
|=
|=
|=
|=
|=
(p q) (p q) (q p)
(p q) (p q) (q p)
(p q) (p q) (q p)
(p q) (p q)
(p q) (p q)
Negation of implication
(p q) (p q)
De Morgan law
(p q) (p q)
De Morgan law
These laws define a method for negating
Negation of implication
Parents: If you behave well you’ll get a new ski at Christmas!
(p q)
Child: I did behave well all the year and there is no ski under the
Christmas tree!
p q
(Did the parents fulfill their promise?)
Attorney general:
If the accused man is guilty then there was an accessory in the fact
Defence lawyer:
It is not true !
Question: Did the advocate (defence lawyer) help the
accused man; what did he actually claim?
(The man is guilty and he performed the illegal act
alone!)
Negation of implication
Sentence in the future tense:
If you steel it I’ll kill you!
It is not true: I will steel it and yet you will not kill me.
(p q)
p q
OK, but:
If the 3rd world war breaks out tomorrow then more than three million
people will be killed.
It is not true: The 3rd world war will break out tomorrow and less than three
million people will be killed ???
Probably by negating the sentence we did not intend to claim that
(certainly) the 3rd world war will break out tomorrow:
There is an unsaid modality: Necessarily, if the 3rd world war breaks
out tomorrow then more than three million people will be killed.
It is not true: Possibly the 3rd world war breaks out tomorrow but at
that case less than three million people will be killed.
Handled by modal logics – not a subject of this course.
Some more arguments
• Transformation from natural language may be
ambiguous:
If a man has high blood pressure and breathes
with difficulties or he has a fever then he is sick.
p – ”X has high blood pressure”
q – ”X breathes with difficulties”
r – ”X has a fever”
s – ”X is sick”
1. possible analysis:
[(p q) r] s
2. possible analysis:
[p (q r)] s
Some more arguments
If Charles has high blood pressure and
breathes with difficulties or he has a fever
then he is sick.
Charles is not sick but he breathes with
difficulties.
What can be deduced from these facts?
We have to distinguish between first and
second reading because they are not
equivalent. The conclusions will be
different.
Analysis of the 1. reading
1. analysis: [(p q) r] s, s, q ???
a) By means of equivalent transformations:
[(p q) r] s, s [(p q) r] (de
transposition
Morgan)
(p q) r (p q), r, but q holds
p, r (consequences)
Hence Charles does not have a high blood
pressure and does not have a fever.
Analysis of the 2. reading
2. analysis: [p (q r)] s, s, q ???
a) reasoning with equivalent transformations:
[p (q r)] s, s [p (q r)]
transposition de Morgan:
p (q r) but q is true the second disjunct
cannot be true the first is true:
p (consequence)
Hence Charles does not have a high blood pressure
(we cannot conclude anything about his
temperature r)
A proof of both cases
1. analysis: [(p q) r] s, s, q |= p,r
2. analysis: [p (q r)] s, s, q |= p
home work
a) 1. case – by means of a table: home work
b) Indirect: premises + negated conclusion (p r)
(p r) and we assume that every f. is true:
•
[(p q) r] s, s, q, p r
•
1 10 1 1
•
0
0
•
0
0
•
0 1
pr=0
contradiction
Summary
• Typical tasks:
–
–
–
–
Verifying a valid argument
What can be deduced from given assumptions?
Add the missing assumptions
Is a given formula a tautology, contradiction,
satisfiable?
– Find models of a formula, find a model of a set of
formulas
• Methods we have learnt till now for PL:
– Table method
– reasoning and equivalent transformation
– Indirect proof
First-order predicate logic
We have seen that the question
“Is a formula A true?”
is reasonable only when we add
“in the interpretation I for a valuation v of free variables”.
Interpretation structure is an n-tuple:
I = U, R1,...,Rn, F1,...,Fm,
where F1,...,Fm are functions over the universe of discourse assigned to
the functional symbols occurring in the formula, and
R1,...,Rn are relations over the universe of discourse assigned to the
predicate symbols occurring in the formula.
How to evaluate the truth-value of a formula in an interpretation
structure I, or for short in the Interpretation I?
4/10/2016
FOPL: Interpretation, models
20
Interpretation, evaluation of a formula
A.
B.
C.
A.
We evaluate bottom up, i.e., from the “inside out” :
First, determine the elements of the universe denoted by terms,
then determine the truth-values of atomic formulas, and
finally, determine the truth-value of the (composed) formula
Evaluation of terms:
Let v be a valuation that associates each variable x with an element
of the universe: v(x) U.
By evaluation e of terms induced by v we obtain an element e(x) of
the universe U that is defined inductively as follows:
e(x) = v(x)
e(f(t1, t2,...,tn)) = F(e(t1), e(t2),...,e(tn)),
where F is the function assigned by I to the functional symbol f.
4/10/2016
FOPL: Interpretation, models
21
Interpretation, evaluation of a formula
Evaluation of a formula
B.
Atomic formulas: |=I P(t1,...,tn)[v] – the formula is true in the
interpretation I for a valuation v iff
e(t1), e(t2),...,e(tn) R,
where R is the relation assigned to the symbol P
(we also say that R is the domain of truth of P)
Composed formulas:
1.
2.
Propositionally composed A, A B, A B, A B, A B,
dtto Propositional Logic
b)
Quantified Formulas xA(x), xA(x):
|=I xA(x)[v], if for any individual i U holds |=I A[v(x/i)],
where v(x/i) is a valuation identical to v up to
assigning the individual i to the variable x
|=I xA(x)[v], if for at least one individual i U holds |=I A[v(x/i)].
a)
4/10/2016
FOPL: Interpretation, models
22
Quantifiers
It is obvious from the definition of quantifiers that over a
finite universe of discourse U = {a1,…,an} the following
equivalences hold:
x A(x) A(a1) … A(an)
x A(x) A(a1) … A(an)
Hence universal quantifier is a generalization of a
conjunction;
existential quantifier is a generalization of a disjunction.
Therefore, the following equivalences obviously holds:
x A(x) x A(x),
x A(x) x A(x)
de Morgan laws
4/10/2016
FOPL: Interpretation, models
23
Satisfiability and validity in interpretation
Formula A is satisfiable in interpretation I, if there exists valuation
v of variables that |=I A[v].
Formula A is true in interpretation I, |=I A, if for all possible
valuations v holds that |=I A[v].
Model of a formula A is an interpretation I, in which A is true
(that means for all valuations of free variables).
Formula A is satisfiable, if there is interpretation I, in which A is
satisfied (i.e., if there is an interpretation I and valuation v such that
|=I A[v].)
Formula A is a tautology (logically valid), |= A, if A is true in every
interpretation (i.e., for all valuations).
Formula A is a contradiction, if there is no interpretation I, that
would satisfy A, so there is no interpretation and valuation, in which
A would be true: |I A[v], for any I and v.
Satisfiability and validity in interpretation
A: x P(f(x), x) B: x P(f(x), x) C: P(f(x), x)
Interpretation I: U=N, f x2, P relation >
It is true that: |=I B. Formula B is in N, x2, > true.
Formulas A and C are in N, >, x2 satisfied, but not true:
for e0(x) = 0, e1(x) = 1 pairs 0,0, 1,1 are not elements of >; for
e2(x) = 2, e3(x) = 3, …, pairs 4,2, 9,3, … are elements of the
relation >.
Formulas A, C are not in N, x2, > true:
|I A[e0], |I A[e1], |I C[e0], |I C[e1],
only:
|=I A[e2], |=I A[e3], |=I C[e2], |=I C[e3], …
Empty universe?
Consider an empty universe U =
x P(x): is it true or not?
By the definition of quantifiers it is false, because we can’t find any
individual which would satisfy P, then it is true that x P(x), so
x P(x), but this is false as well – contradiction.
Or it is true, because there is no element of the universe that would
not have the property P, but then x P(x) should be true as well,
which is false – contradiction.
Likewise for x P(x) leads to a contradiction
So we always choose a non-empty universe of
interpretation
Logic “of an empty world” would not be not reasonable
Existential quantifier + implication?
There is somebody such that if he/she is a genius,
then everybody is a genius.
This sentence cannot be false: |= x (G(x) xG(x))
For every interpretation I it holds:
If the truth-domain GU of the predicate G is equal to the whole
universe (GU = U), then the formula is true in I, because the
subformula xG(x) is true;
hence G(x) x G(x), and x (G(x) xG(x)) is true in I.
If GU is a proper subset of U (GU U), then it suffices to find at
least one individual a (assigned by valuation v to x) such that a is
not an element of GU. Then G(a) x G(x) is true in I, because the
antecedent G(a) is false. Hence
x (G(x) xG(x)) is true in I.
27
Existential quantifier + conjunction !
Similarly x (P(x) Q(x)) is “almost” a tautology. It is
true in every interpretation I such that
PU U, because then |=I P(x) Q(x)[v] for v(x) PU
or QU = U, because then |=I P(x) Q(x) for all valuations
So this formula is false only in such an interpretation I
where PU = U and QU U.
Therefore, sentences of a type
“Some P’s are Q’s”
are analyzed by x (P(x) Q(x)).
Universal quantifier + conjunction? Usually no,
but implication!
Similarly x [P(x) Q(x)] is ”almost” a contradiction!
The formula is false in every interpretation I such that
PU U or QU U.
So the formula is true only in an interpretation I such that PU = U
a QU = U
Therefore, sentences of a type
“All P’s are Q’s“
are analyzed by x [P(x) Q(x)]
It holds for all individuals x that if x is a P then x is a Q.
(See the definition of the subset relation PU QU)
Satisfiability and validity in interpretation
Formula A(x) with a free variable x:
If A(x) is true in I, then |=I x A(x)
If A(x) is satisfied in I, then |=I x A(x).
Formulas P(x) Q(x), P(x) Q(x)
with the free variable x define the intersection and
union, respectively, of truth-domains PU, QU. For every
P, Q, PU, QU and an interpretation I it holds:
|=I x [P(x) Q(x)]
iff
P U QU
|=I x [P(x) Q(x)]
iff
P U QU
|=I x [P(x) Q(x)]
iff
P U QU = U
|=I x [P(x) Q(x)]
iff
P U QU
Model of a set of formulas, logical entailment
A Model of the set of formulas {A1,…,An} is an
interpretation I such that each of the formulas A1,...,An is
true in I.
Formula B logically follows from A1, …, An, denoted
A1,…,An |= B, iff B is true in every model of {A1,…,An}.
Thus for every interpretation I in which the formulas A1,
…, An are true it holds that the formula B is true as well:
A1,…,An |= B: If |=I A1,…, |=I An then |=I B, for all I.
Note that the “circumstances“ under which a formula is,
or is not, true (see the 1st lesson, Definition 1) are in
FOL modelled by interpretations (of predicates and
functional symbols by relations and functions,
respectively, over the universe).
Logical entailment in FOL
P(x) |= x P(x),
but the formula P(x) x P(x) is obviously not a
tautology.
Therefore, A1,...,An |= Z |= (A1… An Z) holds only
for closed formulas, so-called sentences.
x P(x) P(a) is also not a tautology, and thus the rule
x P(x) | P(a) is not truth-preserving;
P(a) does not logically follow form x P(x).
Example of an interpretation I such that x P(x) is, and
P(a) is not true in I:
U = N(atural numbers), P even numbers, a 3
Semantic verification of an argument
An argument is valid iff the conclusion is true
in every model of the set of the premises.
But the set of models can be infinite!
And, of course, we cannot examine an infinite
number of models; but we can verify the
‘logical form’ of the argument, and check
whether the models of premises do satisfy the
conclusion.
Semantic verification of an argument
Example:
All monkeys (P) like bananas (Q)
Judy (a) is monkey
Judy likes bananas
x [P(x) Q(x)]
QU
PU
P(a)
Q(a)
a
Relations
Propositions with unary predicates (expressing
properties of individuals) were studied already in
the ancient times by Aristotle.
Until quite recently Gottlob Frege, the founder
of modern logic, developed the system of formal
predicate logic with n-ary predicates
characterizing relations between individuals, and
with quantifiers.
Frege, however, used another language than
the one of the current FOL.
Aristotle:
(384 BC – March 7, 322 BC)
a Greek philosopher, a student of
Plato and teacher of Alexander
the Great.
He wrote on diverse subjects,
including physics, metaphysics,
poetry (including theater), biology
and zoology, logic, rhetoric,
politics, government, and ethics.
Along with Socrates and Plato,
Aristotle was one of the most
influential of the ancient Greek
philosophers. They transformed
Presocratic Greek philosophy into
the foundations of Western
philosophy as we know it.
Plato and Aristotle have founded
two of the most important schools
of Ancient philosophy.
Gottlob Frege
1848 – 1925
German
mathematician,
logician and
philosopher,
taught at the
University of
Jena.
Founder of modern
logic.
37
Semantic verification of an argument
Marie likes only winners
Karel is a winner
------------------------------------- Marie likes Karel
invalid
x [R(m,x) V(x)], V(k) R(m,k) ?
RU U U: { <Marie, i1>, <Marie, i2>, …, <Marie, in> …}
VU U:
{…i1, i2, …, Karel,…, in…}
The pair <Marie, Karel> doesn’t have to be an element of
RU, it is not guaranteed by the validity of the premises.
Being a winner is only a necessary condition for Marie’s
liking somebody, but it is not a sufficient condition.
Semantic verification of an argument
Marie likes only winners
Karel is not a winner
------------------------------------ Marie does not like Karel
valid
x [R(m,x) V(x)], V(k) R(m,k)
RU U U:
{…<Marie, i1>, <Marie, i2>, <Marie, Karel>, …, <Marie, in> …}
VU U:
{…i1, i2, …, Karel, Karel,…, in…}
Let the pair <Marie, Karel> be an element of RU;
then by the first premise Karel has to be an element of VU, but
it is not so if the second premise is true.
Hence the pair <Marie, Karel> is not an element of RU.
The validity of the conclusion is guaranteed by the validity of premises.
Semantic verification of an argument
Anybody who knows Marie and Karel is sorry for Marie.
x [(K(x,m) K(x,k)) S(x,m)]
Some are not sorry for Marie though they know her.
x [S(x,m) K(x,m)]
|= Somebody knows Marie but not Karel.
x [K(x,m) K(x,k)]
We illustrate the truth-domain of the predicates K and S,
i.e., the relations KU and SU that satisfy the premises:
KU = {…, i1,m, i1,k, i2,m, i2,k,…, ,m,… }
1. premise
2. premise
SU = {…, i1,m, ...., i2,m,…........., ,m,… }
Semantic verification of an argument: an indirect proof
Anybody who knows Marie and Karel
is sorry for Marie.
Some are not sorry for Marie
though they know her.
|= Somebody knows Marie but not Karel.
x [(K(x,m) K(x,k)) S(x,m)]
x [S(x,m) K(x,m)]
x [K(x,m) K(x,k)]
Assume now that all the individuals who are paired with m in KU are
also paired with k in KU:
KU = {…, i1,m, i1,k, i2,m, i2,k,…, ,m, ,k … }
SU = {…, i1,m, ...., i2,m,…........., ,m, ,m … }
contradiction
Some important tautologies of FOL
|= xAx Ax/t
|= Ax/t xAx
De Morgan
|= x Ax x Ax
|= x Ax x Ax
term t is substitutable for x in A
The laws of quantifier distribution:
|= x [A(x) B(x)] [x A(x) x B(x)]
|= x [A(x) B(x)] [x A(x) x B(x)]
|= x [A(x) B(x)] [x A(x) x B(x)]
|= x [A(x) B(x)] [x A(x) x B(x)]
|= [xA(x) xB(x)] x [A(x) B(x)]
|= x [A(x) B(x)] [x A(x) x B(x)]
Semantic proofs: Let AU, BU be truth-domains of A, B
x[A(x) B(x)] [xA(x) xB(x)]
If the intersection (AU BU) = U, then AU and BU must be equal to the
whole universe U, and vice-versa.
x[A(x) B(x)] [xA(x) xB(x)]
If the union (AU BU) , then AU or BU must be non-empty (AU ,
or BU ), and vice-versa.
|= x[A(x) B(x)] [xA(x) xB(x)]
If AU BU, then if AU = U then BU = U.
|= x[A(x) B(x)] [xA(x) xB(x)]
If AU BU, then if AU then BU .
|= x[A(x) B(x)] [xA(x) xB(x)]
If the intersection (AU BU) , then AU and BU must be non-empty
(AU , BU ).
|= [xA(x) xB(x)] x[A(x) B(x)]
If AU = U or BU = U, then the union (AU BU) = U
Some important tautologies
Formula A does not contain free variable x:
|= x[A B(x)] [A xB(x)]
|= x[A B(x)] [A xB(x)]
|= x[B(x) A] [xB(x) A]
|= x[B(x) A] [xB(x) A]
|= x[A B(x)] [A xB(x)]
|= x[A B(x)] [A xB(x)]
|= x[A B(x)] [A xB(x)]
|= x[A B(x)] [A xB(x)]
The commutative law of quantifiers.
|= xyA(x,y) yxA(x,y)
|= xyA(x,y) yxA(x,y)
|= xyA(x,y) yxA(x,y)
but not vice-versa!
Semantic proofs: Let AU, BU be truth- domains of A, B (x
not free in A
x[A B(x)] [A xB(x)] – obvious
x[A B(x)] [A xB(x)] – obvious
x [B(x) A] [x B(x) A]
x [B(x) A] x [B(x) A]: the complement BU or
A is the whole universe: x B(x) A
x B(x) A x B(x) A
x[B(x) A] [xB(x) A]
x [B(x) A] x [B(x) A]: the complement BU is
non-empty or A: x B(x) A
x B(x) A x B(x) A
Typical problems
Prove the logical validity of a formula:
Prove the validity of an argument:
A formula F is true in all interpretations, which means that
every interpretation is a model
|= F
P1, …, Pn |= Q
for close formulas iff |= (P1 … Pn Q)
formula Q is true in all the models of the set of premises
P1, …, Pn
What is entailed by the given premises?
P1, …, Pn |= ?
Typical problems
Semantic solution over an infinite set of models
is difficult, semantics proofs are tough.
So we are trying to find some other methods
One of them is the semantic-tableau method.
Analogy, generalization of the same method in
propositional logic
Transformation to a disjunctive / conjunctive
normal form.
Semantic tableau in FOL
When proving a tautology by
a direct proof – we use a conjunctive normal form
an indirect proof – disjunctive normal form
In order to apply the propositional logic method of
semantic tableau, we have to get rid of quantifiers.
How to eliminate them?
To this end we use the following rules:
x A(x) | A(x/t), where t is a term which is
substitutable for x in A, usually t = x
(x)A(x) | A(a), where a is a new constant (not used
in the proof as yet)
Rules for quantifiers elimination
x A(x) | A(x/t), term t is substitutable for x
If the truth-domain AU = U, then the individual e(t) is an element of AU
The rule is truth-preserving, OK
(x)A(x) | A(a), where a is a new constant
If the truth-domain AU , the individual e(a) might not be an element
of AU
The rule is not truth-preserving!
x (y) B(x,y) | B(a, b), where a, b are suitable constants
Though if for every x there is a y such that the pair <x,y> is in BU, the
pair <a, b> might not be an element of BU.
The rule is not truth-preserving!
However, existential-quantifier elimination does not yield a contradiction: it is
possible to interpret the constants a, b so that the formula on the right-hand
side is true, whenever the formula on the left-hand side is true.
For this reason we use the indirect proof (disjunctive tableau), whenever the
premises contain existential quantifier(s)
Semantic tableau in FOL– disjunctive
Example. Proof of the logical validity of a formula:
|= x [P(x) Q(x)] [x P(x) x Q(x)]
Indirect proof (non-satisfiable of formula):
x [P(x) Q(x)] x P(x) x Q(x)
(order!)
2.
3.
1.
x [P(x) Q(x)], P(a) Q(a), P(a), Q(a)
x [P(x) Q(x)], P(a), P(a), Q(a)
x [P(x) Q(x)], Q(a), P(a), Q(a)
+
+
Both branches are closed, they are contradictory. Therefore, the original
(blue) formula is tautology.
Semantic tableau
|=? x [P(x) Q(x)] [x P(x) x Q(x)]
Negation:
x [P(x) Q(x)] x P(x) x Q(x)
x [P(x) Q(x)], P(a), Q(b)
P(a) Q(a), P(b) Q(b), P(a), Q(b)
P(a), P(b) Q(b), P(a), Q(b)
P(a), P(b), P(a), Q(b)
1.eliminaton - diff. const. !
2. elimination
Q(a), P(b) Q(b), P(a), Q(b)
P(a), Q(b), P(a), Q(b)
Q(a), P(b), P(a), Q(b)
Q(a), Q(b), P(a), Q(b)
Formula is not logically valid, 3. branch is not closed
Tableau can lead to an infinite evaluation
F: x y P(x,y) x P(x,x)
x y z ([P(x,y) P(y,z)] P(x,z))
Variable x is bound by universal quantifier
We must “check all x” : a1, a2, a3, …
For y we must choose always another constant:
P(a1, a2), P(a1, a1)
P(a2, a3), P(a2, a2), P(a2, a1)
P(a3, a4), P(a3, a3), P(a3, a2)
P(a4, a5), P(a4, a4), P(a4, a3)
…
The problem of logical validity is not decidable in
FOL
Tableau can lead to an infinite evaluation
1.
2.
F: x y P(x,y) x P(x,x)
x y z ([P(x,y) P(y,z)] P(x,z))
What kind of formula is F? Is it satisfiable, contradictory or logicaly valid?
Try to find a model:
U=N
PU = relation < (less then)
1 2 3 4 5 ...
satisfiable
Could the formula F have a finite model?
U = {a1, a2, a3, ... ? }
To a1 there must exist an element a2, so that P(a1, a2), a2 a1
To a2 there must exist an element a3 such that P(a2, a3), a3 a2, and a3 a1
otherwise P(a1, a2) P(a2, a1), so P(a1, a1).
To a3 there must exist an element a4 such that P(a3, a4), a4 a3, and a4 a2
otherwise P(a2, a3) P(a3, a2), so P(a2, a2).
And so on ad infinitum…
Argument validity- indirect proof
x [P(x) Q(x)] x Q(x) |= x P(x)
x [P(x) Q(x)], x Q(x), x P(x) – contradictory?
x [P(x) Q(x)], Q(a), x P(x)
x [P(x) Q(x)], x P(x), [P(a) Q(a)], Q(a), P(a)
P(a), Q(a), P(a)
Q(a), Q(a), P(a)
+
+
Both branches are closed. The set of premises together with
the negated conclusion is contradictory; so the argument is
valid…
Argument validity- indirect proof
x [P(x) Q(x)] x Q(x) |= x P(x)
No whale is fish.
The fish exists.
Some individuals are not the whales.
The set of statements:
{No whale is fish, fish exists, all individuals
are whales}
is contradictory.
Consistency checking
There is a barber who shaves just those who do
not shave themselves
Does the barber shave himself?
x y [H(y,y) H(x,y)] |= ?
H(y,y) H(a,y), H(y,y) H(a,y) – eliminating
H(a,a) H(a,a), H(a,a) H(a,a) – eliminating
H(a,a), H(a,a) H(a,a), H(a,a), H(a,a) H(a,a)
H(a,a), H(a,a)
H(a,a), H(a,a) …
+
The first sentence is contradictory; anything is entailed by
it. But, such a barber does not exist.
Summary – semantic tableau in FOL
We use semantic tableaus for an indirect proof, i.e., transform a
formula to the disjunctive normal form
(branching means disjunction, comma conjunction)
There is a problem with closed formulas. We need to eliminate
quantifiers.
First, eliminate existential quantifiers: replace the variable (which is not
in the scope of any universal quantifier) by a new constant that is still
not used.
Second, eliminate universal quantifiers: replace the universally bound
variables step by step by suitable constants, until a contradiction
emerges, i.e., the branch gets closed
If a variable x is bound by an existential quantifier and x is in the scope
of a universal quantifier binding a variable y, we must gradually replace
y by suitable constants and consequently the variable x by new, not
used constants …
If the tableau eventually gets closed, the formula or a set of formulas is
contradictory.
Example – semantic tableau
|= xy P(x,y) yx P(x,y)
negation: xy P(x,y) yx P(x,y)
yP(a,y), xP(x,b)
x/a, y/b (for all…, hence also for a, b)
P(a,b), P(a,b)
+
Example – semantic tableau
|= [x P(x) x Q(x)] x [P(x) Q(x)]
negation: [x P(x) x Q(x)] x [P(x) Q(x)]
x P(x), P(a), Q(a)
x Q(x), P(a), Q(a)
xP(x),P(a),P(a),Q(a)
+
xQ(x),Q(a),P(a),Q(a)
+
Gottlob Frege
Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (b. 1848, d. 1925) was a German mathematician,
logician, and philosopher who worked at the University of Jena.
Frege essentially reconceived the discipline of logic by constructing a formal
system which, in effect, constituted the first ‘predicate calculus’. In this formal
system, Frege developed an analysis of quantified statements and formalized the
notion of a ‘proof’ in terms that are still accepted today.
Frege then demonstrated that one could use his system to resolve theoretical
mathematical statements in terms of simpler logical and mathematical notions.
Bertrand Russell showed that of the axioms that Frege later added to his system,
in the attempt to derive significant parts of mathematics from logic, proved to be
inconsistent.
Nevertheless, his definitions (of the predecessor relation and of the concept of
natural number) and methods (for deriving the axioms of number theory)
constituted a significant advance. To ground his views about the relationship of
logic and mathematics, Frege conceived a comprehensive philosophy of language
that many philosophers still find insightful. However, his lifelong project, of showing
that mathematics was reducible to logic, was not successful.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/frege/
60
Bertrand Russell
1872-1970
British philosopher, logician,
essay-writer
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell (b.1872 - d.1970) was
a British philosopher, logician, essayist, and social
critic, best known for his work in mathematical logic
and analytic philosophy. His most influential
contributions include his defense of logicism (the
view that mathematics is in some important sense
reducible to logic), and his theories of definite
descriptions and logical atomism. Along with G.E.
Moore, Russell is generally recognized as one of the
founders of analytic philosophy. Along with Kurt
Gödel, he is also regularly credited with being one
of the two most important logicians of the twentieth
century.
Kurt Gödel (1906-Brno, 1978-Princeton)
The greatest logician of 20th century, a friend of A. Einstein,
became famous by his Incompleteness Theorems of arithmetic
Russell's Paradox
Russell's paradox is the most famous of the
logical or set-theoretical paradoxes. The
paradox arises within naive set theory by
considering the set of all sets that are not
members of themselves. Such a set appears
to be a member of itself if and only if it is not
a member of itself, hence the paradox.
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/russellparadox/
Russell's Paradox
Some sets, such as the set of all teacups, are not
members of themselves. Other sets, such as the set
of all non-teacups, are members of themselves. Call
the set of all sets that are not members of
themselves "R." If R is a member of itself, then by
definition it must not be a member of itself. Similarly,
if R is not a member of itself, then by definition it
must be a member of itself. Discovered by Bertrand
Russell in 1901, the paradox has prompted much
work in logic, set theory and the philosophy and
foundations of mathematics.
Russell's Paradox
R – the set of all normal sets that are not members of
themselves
Question: “Is R normal?” yields a contradiction.
In symbols: xR (xx) – by the definition of R
The question R R? yields a contradiction:
RR RR, because:
Answer YES – R is not normal, RR, but by the
definition R is not a member of R, i.e. RR
Answer NO – R is normal, RR, but then by the
definition RR
(because R is the set of all normal sets)
Russell wrote to Gottlob Frege with news of his
paradox on June 16, 1902. The paradox was of
significance to Frege's logical work since, in effect, it
showed that the axioms Frege was using to
formalize his logic were inconsistent.
Specifically, Frege's Rule V, which states that two sets
are equal if and only if their corresponding functions
coincide in values for all possible arguments,
requires that an expression such as f(x) be
considered both a function of the argument x and a
function of the argument f. In effect, it was this
ambiguity that allowed Russell to construct R in
such a way that it could both be and not be a
member of itself.
Russell's Paradox
Russell's letter arrived just as the second volume of Frege's Grundgesetze der
Arithmetik (The Basic Laws of Arithmetic, 1893, 1903) was in press.
Immediately appreciating the difficulty the paradox posed, Frege added to the
Grundgesetze a hastily composed appendix discussing Russell's discovery.
In the appendix Frege observes that the consequences of Russell's paradox
are not immediately clear. For example, "Is it always permissible to speak of
the extension of a concept, of a class? And if not, how do we recognize the
exceptional cases? Can we always infer from the extension of one concept's
coinciding with that of a second, that every object which falls under the first
concept also falls under the second? These are the questions," Frege notes,
"raised by Mr Russell's communication." Because of these worries, Frege
eventually felt forced to abandon many of his views about logic and
mathematics.
Of course, Russell also was concerned about the contradiction. Upon learning
that Frege agreed with him about the significance of the result, he
immediately began writing an appendix for his own soon-to-be-released
Principles of Mathematics. Entitled "Appendix B: The Doctrine of Types," the
appendix represents Russell's first detailed attempt at providing a principled
method for avoiding what was soon to become known as "Russell's paradox."
68
Russell's Paradox
The significance of Russell's paradox can be seen once it is realized that, using
classical logic, all sentences follow from a contradiction. For example, assuming both
P and ~P, any arbitrary proposition, Q, can be proved as follows: from P we obtain P
Q by the rule of Addition; then from P Q and ~P we obtain Q by the rule of Disjunctive
Syllogism. Because of this, and because set theory underlies all branches of
mathematics, many people began to worry that, if set theory was inconsistent, no
mathematical proof could be trusted completely.
Russell's paradox ultimately stems from the idea that any coherent condition may be used
to determine a set. As a result, most attempts at resolving the paradox have
concentrated on various ways of restricting the principles governing set existence
found within naive set theory, particularly the so-called Comprehension (or Abstraction)
axiom. This axiom in effect states that any propositional function, P(x), containing x as
a free variable can be used to determine a set. In other words, corresponding to every
propositional function, P(x), there will exist a set whose members are exactly those
things, x, that have property P. It is now generally, although not universally, agreed that
such an axiom must either be abandoned or modified.
Russell's own response to the paradox was his aptly named theory of types. Recognizing
that self-reference lies at the heart of the paradox, Russell's basic idea is that we can
avoid commitment to R (the set of all sets that are not members of themselves) by
arranging all sentences (or, equivalently, all propositional functions) into a hierarchy.
The lowest level of this hierarchy will consist of sentences about individuals. The next
lowest level will consist of sentences about sets of individuals. The next lowest level
will consist of sentences about sets of sets of individuals, and so on. It is then possible
to refer to all objects for which a given condition (or predicate) holds only if they are all
at the same level or of the same "type."
69
Russell’s paradox – 3 solutions
Russell's own response to the paradox was his aptly named theory of types.
Recognizing that self-reference lies at the heart of the paradox, Russell's basic
idea is that we can avoid commitment to R (the set of all sets that are not
members of themselves) by arranging all sentences (or, equivalently, all
propositional functions) into a hierarchy. The lowest level of this hierarchy will
consist of sentences about individuals. The next lowest level will consist of
sentences about sets of individuals. The next lowest level will consist of
sentences about sets of sets of individuals, and so on. It is then possible to refer
to all objects for which a given condition (or predicate) holds only if they are all at
the same level or of the same "type."
This solution to Russell's paradox is motivated in large part by the so-called vicious
circle principle, a principle which, in effect, states that no propositional function
can be defined prior to specifying the function's range. In other words, before a
function can be defined, one first has to specify exactly those objects to which the
function will apply. (For example, before defining the predicate "is a prime
number," one first needs to define the range of objects that this predicate might
be said to satisfy, namely the set, N, of natural numbers.) From this it follows that
no function's range will ever be able to include any object defined in terms of the
function itself. As a result, propositional functions (along with their corresponding
propositions) will end up being arranged in a hierarchy of exactly the kind Russell
proposes.
70
Russell’s paradox – 3 solutions
Although Russell first introduced his theory of types in his 1903 Principles of
Mathematics, type theory found its mature expression five years later in his 1908
article, "Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types," and in the
monumental work he co-authored with Alfred North Whitehead, Principia
Mathematica (1910, 1912, 1913). Russell's type theory thus appears in two
versions: the "simple theory" of 1903 and the "ramified theory" of 1908. Both
versions have been criticized for being too ad hoc to eliminate the paradox
successfully. In addition, even if type theory is successful in eliminating Russell's
paradox, it is likely to be ineffective at resolving other, unrelated paradoxes.
Other responses to Russell's paradox have included those of David Hilbert and the
formalists (whose basic idea was to allow the use of only finite, well-defined and
constructible objects, together with rules of inference deemed to be absolutely
certain), and of Luitzen Brouwer and the intuitionists (whose basic idea was
that one cannot assert the existence of a mathematical object unless one can also
indicate how to go about constructing it).
Yet a fourth response was embodied in Ernst Zermelo's 1908 axiomatization of set
theory. Zermelo's axioms were designed to resolve Russell's paradox by again
restricting the Comprehension axiom in a manner not dissimilar to that proposed
by Russell. ZF and ZFC (i.e., ZF supplemented by the Axiom of Choice), the two
axiomatizations generally used today, are modifications of Zermelo's theory
developed primarily by Abraham Fraenkel.
71
Thank you for your attention
See you next week