Methods of Proof for Quantifiers
Download
Report
Transcript Methods of Proof for Quantifiers
Language, Proof and
Logic
Methods of Proof for
Quantifiers
Chapter 12
12.1
Valid quantifier steps
Universal elimination (instantiation):
From xP(x) infer P(c)
Existential introduction (generalization):
From P(c) infer xP(x)
1. x[Cube(x)Large(x)]
2. x[Large(x)LeftOf(x,b)]
3. Cube(d)
4. x[Large(x)LeftOf(x,b)]
where c is the name
of some object of the
domain of discourse
3 says that d is a cube. And
1 says that all cubes are large.
Thus, d is large. But 2 says
that every large object is to
the left of b. So, d is to the
left of b. To summarize,
d is large and is to the left of b.
Thus, there is a large object to
the left of b.
Let us think about whether there is any similarity with -elim and -intro.
12.2
The method of existential instantiation
Existential instantiation (elimination): Once you have proven xP(x)
(or have it as a premise), you can select a “neutral” (not used elsewhere)
name d and use P(d) as a valid assumption.
1. x[Cube(x)Large(x)]
2. x[Large(x)LeftOf(x,b)]
3. xCube(x)
4. x[Large(x)LeftOf(x,b)]
Important: If we had selected
d=b, we would have been able to
“prove” xLeftOf(x,x)!
3 says that there is a cube. Let d
be such a cube, i.e. assume
Cube(d) (is true).
1 says that all cubes are large.
Thus, d is large. But 2 says
that every large object is to
the left of b. So, d is to the
left of b. To summarize,
d is large and is to the left of b.
Thus, there is a large object to
the left of b.
Let us think about whether there is any similarity with -elim.
12.3.a
The method of general conditional proof
Universal generalization (introduction): Once you have proven P(d) for
some “neutral” (not used elsewhere) name d (denoting a “totally
arbitrary” object), you can conclude xP(x).
1. xLarge(x)
2. x[Large(x)SameRow(x,b)]
3. xSameRow(x,b)
Important: The “arbitrary” object
d indeed has to be arbitrary. Things
will go wrong if you select d=b here
Consider any object d. By 1, d is
large. But, by 2, every large
object is in the same row as b. So,
d is in the same row as b. As d
was arbitrary, we conclude that
every object is in the same row
as b.
1. Cube(b)
2. x[Cube(x)Large(x)]
3. xLarge(x)
Let us think about whether there is any similarity with -intro.
12.3.b
The method of general conditional proof
General conditional proof: Once you have proven Q(d) from the
assumption P(d) for some “neutral” (not used elsewhere) name d
(denoting a “totally arbitrary” object), you can conclude x[P(x)Q(x)].
1. x[Cube(x)SameRow(x,b)]
2. x[SameRow(x,b)Small(x)]
3. x[Cube(x)Small(x)]
Consider any object d, and assume d
is a cube. 1 says that every cube is in
the same row as b. So, d is in the same
row as b. But, by 2, everything in the
same row as b is small. So, d is small.
As d was arbitrary, we conclude that
every cube is small.
Let us think about why universal generalization in fact makes this rule redundant.
12.4.a
Proofs involving mixed quantifiers
1. y[Girl(y) x(Boy(x) Likes(x,y))]
2. x[Boy(x) y(Girl(y) Likes(x,y))]
Consider an arbitrary boy d. By 1, there is a girl who is liked by every
boy. Let c be such a girl. So, d likes c. That is, d likes some girl. As
d was arbitrary, we conclude that every boy likes some girl.
1. x[Boy(x) y(Girl(y) Likes(x,y))]
2. y[Girl(y) x(Boy(x) Likes(x,y))]
Pseudo-proof: Consider an arbitrary boy d. By 1, d likes some girl. Let
c be such a girl. Thus, d likes c. Since d was arbitrary, we conclude that
every boy likes c. So, there is a girl (specifically, c) who is liked
by every boy.
12.4.b
Proofs involving mixed quantifiers
REMEMBER
Let P(x), Q(x) be wffs.
1. Existential Instantiation: If you have proven xP(x) then you may
choose a new constant symbol c to stand for any object satisfying
P(x) and so you may assume P(c).
2. General Conditional Proof: If you want to prove x[P(x)Q(x)]
then you may choose a new constant symbol c, assume P(c), and
prove Q(c), making sure that Q does not contain any names
introduced by existential instantiation after the assumption of P(c).
3. Universal Generalization: If you want to prove xQ(x) then you
may choose a new constant symbol c and prove Q(c), making sure
that Q does not contain any names introduced by existential
instantiation after the introduction of c.
12.4.c
Proofs involving mixed quantifiers
Euclid’s Theorem: xy[yx Prime(y)]
Proof. Consider an arbitrary natural number n. Our goal is to show that
y[yn Prime(y)], from which Euclid’s theorem follows by universal
generalization.
Let k be the product of all the prime numbers less than n. Thus each
prime with <n divides k without remainder. Now let m=k+1. Each
prime less than n divides m with remainder 1. But we know that m can
be factored into primes. Let p be one of those primes. Clearly, by the
earlier observation, pn. Hence, by existential generalization, there
is a prime (specifically, p) greater or equal to n.
As n was arbitrary, we conclude that xy[yx Prime(y)].
12.4.d
Proofs involving mixed quantifiers
The Barber Paradox:
xy [Shave(x,y) Shave(y,y)]
The domain of discourse is the set of all men in a small village.
Proof. Assume, for a contradiction, that
1. xy [Shave(x,y) Shave(y,y)]
Let b be a man (barber) such that
2. y [Shave(b,y) Shave(y,y)]
is true. By universal instantiation from 2,
3. Shave(b,b) Shave(b,b).
But this is (indeed) a contradiction.