Transcript chapter9
CS 2710, ISSP 2160
Chapter 9
Inference in First-Order Logic
1
Pages to skim
• Storage and Retrieval (p. starts bottom 328)
• Efficient forward chaining (starts p. 333) through
Irrelevant facts (ends top 337)
• Efficient implementation of logic programs (starts p. 340)
through Constraint logic programming (ends p. 345)
• Completeness of resolution (starts p. 350) (though see notes
in slides)
2
Inference with Quantifiers
• Universal Instantiation:
– Given X (person(X) likes(X, sun))
– Infer person(john) likes(john,sun)
• Existential Instantiation:
– Given x likes(x, chocolate)
– Infer: likes(S1, chocolate)
– S1 is a “Skolem Constant” that is not found anywhere else
in the KB and refers to (one of) the individuals that likes
sun.
3
Reduction to Propositional Inference
• Simple form (pp. 324-325) not efficient. Useful
conceptually.
• Replace each universally quantified sentence by all possible
instantiations
– All X (man(X) mortal(X)) replaced by
– man(tom) mortal(tom)
– man(chocolate) mortal(chocolate)
– …
• Now, we have propositional logic.
• Use propositional reasoning algorithms from Ch 7
4
Reduction to Propositional Inference
• Problem: when the KB includes a function symbol, the set of
term substitutions is infinite. father(father(father(tom)))
…
• Herbrand 1930: if a sentence is entailed by the original FO
KB, then there is a proof using a finite subset of the
propositionalized KB
• Since any subset has a maximum depth of nesting in terms,
we can find the subset by generating all instantiations with
constant symbols, then all with depth 1, and so on
5
First-Order Inference
• We have an approach to FO inference via
propositionalization that is complete: any entailed sentence
can be proved
• Entailment for FOPC is semi-decidable: algorithms exist that
say yes to every entailed sentence, but no algorithm exists
that also says no to every nonentailed sentence.
• Our proof procedure could go on and on, generating more and
more deeply nested terms, but we will not know whether it is
stuck in a loop, or whether the proof is just about to pop out
6
Generalized Modus Ponens
• This is a general inference rule for FOPC that does not
require universal instantiation first
• Given:
– p1’, p2’ … pn’, (p1 … pn) q
– Subst(theta, pi’) = subst(theta, pi) for all i
• Conclude:
– Subst(theta, q)
7
GMP is a lifted version of MP
• GMP “lifts” MP from propositional to first-order logic
• Key advantage of lifted inference rules over
propositionalization is that they make only substitutions
which are required to allow particular inferences to proceed
8
GMP Example
• x,y,z ((parent(x,y) parent(y,z)) grandparent(x,z))
• parent(james, john), parent(james, richard), parent(harry,
james)
• We can derive:
– Grandparent(harry, john), bindings:
{x/harry,y/james,z/john}
– Grandparent(harry, richard), bindings:
{x/harry,y/james,z/richard}
9
Unification
• Process of finding all legal substitutions
• Key component of all FO inference algorithms
• Unify(p,q) = theta, where Subst(theta,p) == Subst(theta,q)
Assuming all variables universally quantified
10
Standardizing apart
• All X knows(john,X).
• All X knows(X,elizabeth).
• These ought to unify, since john knows everyone, and
everyone knows elizabeth.
• Rename variables to avoid such name clashes
Note:
all X p(X) == all Y p(Y)
All X (p(X) ^ q(X)) == All X p(X) ^ All Y q(Y)
11
def Unify (p, q, bdgs):
d = disagreement(p, q)
# If there is no disagreement, then success.
if not d: return bdgs
elif not isVar(d[0]) and not isVar(d[1]): return 'fail'
else:
if isVar(d[0]): var = d[0] ; other = d[1]
else: var = d[1] ; other = d[0]
if occursp (var,other): return ‘fail’
# Make appropriate substitutions and recurse on the result.
else:
pp = replaceAll(var,other,p)
qq = replaceAll(var,other,q)
return Unify (pp,qq, bdgs + [[var,other]])
For code, see “resources” on the webpage
12
================================
unify:
['loves', ['dog', 'var_x'], ['dog', 'fred']]
['loves', 'var_z', 'var_z']
subs: [['var_z', ['dog', 'var_x']], ['var_x', 'fred']]
result: ['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], ['dog', 'fred']]
================================
unify:
['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], 'fred']
['loves', 'var_x', 'var_y']
subs: [['var_x', ['dog', 'fred']], ['var_y', 'fred']]
result: ['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], 'fred']
================================
unify:
['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], 'mary']
['loves', ['dog', 'var_x'], 'var_y']
subs: [['var_x', 'fred'], ['var_y', 'mary']]
result: ['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], 'mary']
================================
13
unify:
['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], 'mary']
['loves', ['dog', 'var_x'], 'var_y']
subs: [['var_x', 'fred'], ['var_y', 'mary']]
result: ['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], 'mary']
================================
unify:
['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], 'fred']
['loves', 'var_x', 'var_x']
failure
================================
unify:
['loves', ['dog', 'fred'], 'mary']
['loves', ['dog', 'var_x'], 'var_x']
failure
================================
unify:
['loves', 'var_x', 'fred']
['loves', ['dog', 'var_x'], 'fred']
var_x occurs in ['dog', 'var_x']
failure
14
unify:
['loves', 'var_x', ['dog', 'var_x']]
['loves', 'var_y', 'var_y']
var_y occurs in ['dog', 'var_y']
failure
================================
unify:
['loves', 'var_y', 'var_y']
['loves', 'var_x', ['dog', 'var_x']]
var_x occurs in ['dog', 'var_x']
failure
================================
unify: (fails because vars not standardized apart)
['hates', 'agatha', 'var_x']
['hates', 'var_x', ['f1', 'var_x']]
failure
================================
unify:
['hates', 'agatha', 'var_x']
['hates', 'var_y', ['f1', 'var_y']]
subs: [['var_y', 'agatha'], ['var_x', ['f1', 'agatha']]]
result: ['hates', 'agatha', ['f1', 'agatha']]
15
Most General Unifier
• The Unify algorithm returns a MGU
L1 = p(X,f(Y),b)
L2 = p(X,f(b),b)
Subst1 = {X\a, Y\b}
Result1 = p(a,f(b),b)
Subst2 = {Y\b}
Result2 = p(X,f(b),b)
Subst1 is more restrictive than Subst2. In fact,
Subst2 is a MGU of L1 and L2.
16
Storage and retrieval
• Hash statements by predicate for quick retrieval (predicate
indexing), e.g., of all sentences that unify with tall(X)
• Why attempt to unify
– tall(X) and silly(dog(Y))
• Instead
– Predicates[tall] = {all tall facts}
– Unify(tall(X),s) for s in Predicates[tall]
• Subsumption lattice for efficiency (see p. 329 for your
interest)
17
Inference Methods
• Unification (prerequisite)
• Forward Chaining
– Production Systems
– RETE Method (OPS)
• Backward Chaining
– Logic Programming (Prolog)
• Resolution
– Transform to CNF
– Generalization of Prop. Logic resolution
18
Resolution Theorem Proving (FOL)
• Convert everything to CNF
• Resolve, with unification
– Save bindings as you go!
• If resolution is successful, proof succeeds
• If there was a variable in the item to prove, return
variable’s value from unification bindings
19
Converting to CNF
20
Converting sentences to CNF
1. Eliminate all ↔ connectives
(P ↔ Q) ((P Q) ^ (Q P))
2. Eliminate all connectives
(P Q) (P Q)
3. Reduce the scope of each negation symbol to a single predicate
P P
(P Q) P Q
(P Q) P Q
(x)P (x)P
(x)P (x)P
4. Standardize variables: rename all variables so that each quantifier
has its own unique variable name
21
Converting sentences to clausal form: Skolem
constants and functions
5. Eliminate existential quantification by introducing Skolem
constants/functions
(x)P(x) P(c)
c is a Skolem constant (a brand-new constant symbol that is not used
in any other sentence)
(x)(y)P(x,y) becomes (x)P(x, F(x))
since is within the scope of a universally quantified variable, use a
Skolem function F to construct a new value that depends on the
universally quantified variable
f must be a brand-new function name not occurring in any other sentence
in the KB.
E.g., (x)(y)loves(x,y) becomes (x)loves(x,F(x))
In this case, F(x) specifies the person that x loves
E.g., x1 x2 x3 y P(… y …) becomes
x1 x2 x3 P(… FF(x1,x2,x3) …) (FF is a new name)
22
Converting sentences to clausal form
6. Remove universal quantifiers by (1) moving them all to the
left end; (2) making the scope of each the entire sentence;
and (3) dropping the “prefix” part
Ex: (x)P(x) P(x)
7. Put into conjunctive normal form (conjunction of
disjunctions) using distributive and associative laws
(P Q) R (P R) (Q R)
(P Q) R (P Q R)
8. Split conjuncts into separate clauses
9. Standardize variables so each clause contains only variable
names that do not occur in any other clause
23
An example
(x)(P(x) ((y)(P(y) P(F(x,y))) (y)(Q(x,y) P(y))))
2. Eliminate
(x)(P(x) ((y)(P(y) P(F(x,y))) (y)(Q(x,y) P(y))))
3. Reduce scope of negation
(x)(P(x) ((y)(P(y) P(F(x,y))) (y)(Q(x,y) P(y))))
4. Standardize variables
(x)(P(x) ((y)(P(y) P(F(x,y))) (z)(Q(x,z) P(z))))
5. Eliminate existential quantification
(x)(P(x) ((y)(P(y) P(F(x,y))) (Q(x,G(x)) P(G(x)))))
6. Drop universal quantification symbols
(P(x) ((P(y) P(F(x,y))) (Q(x,G(x)) P(G(x)))))
24
An Example
7. Convert to conjunction of disjunctions
(P(x) P(y) P(F(x,y))) (P(x) Q(x,G(x)))
(P(x) P(G(x)))
8. Create separate clauses
P(x) P(y) P(F(x,y))
P(x) Q(x,G(x))
P(x) P(G(x))
9. Standardize variables
P(x) P(y) P(F(x,y))
P(z) Q(z,G(z))
P(w) P(G(w))
Note: Now that quantifiers are gone, we do need the upper/lower-case
distinction
25
1. all X (read (X) --> literate (X))
2. all X (dolphin (X) --> ~literate (X))
3. exists X (dolphin (X) ^ intelligent (X))
(a translation of ``Some dolphins are intelligent'')
``Are there some who are intelligent but cannot read?''
4. exists X (intelligent(X) ^ ~read (X))
Set of clauses (1-3):
1. ~read(X) v literate(X)
2. ~dolphin(Y) v ~literate(Y)
3a. dolphin (a)
3b. intelligent (a)
Negation of 4:
~(exists Z (intelligent(Z) ^ ~read (Z)))
In Clausal form:
~intelligent(Z) v read(Z)
Resolution proof: in lecture.
26
More complicated example
Did Curiosity kill the cat
• Jack owns a dog. Every dog owner is an animal lover. No
animal lover kills an animal. Either Jack or Curiosity killed the
cat, who is named Tuna. Did Curiosity kill the cat?
• These can be represented as follows:
A. (x) (Dog(x) Owns(Jack,x))
B. (x) (((y) (Dog(y) Owns(x, y))) AnimalLover(x))
C. (x) (AnimalLover(x) ((y) Animal(y) Kills(x,y)))
D. Kills(Jack,Tuna) Kills(Curiosity,Tuna)
E. Cat(Tuna)
F. (x) (Cat(x) Animal(x) )
G. Kills(Curiosity, Tuna)
GOAL
27
• Convert to clause form
A1. (Dog(D))
D is a skolem constant
A2. (Owns(Jack,D))
B. (Dog(y), Owns(x, y), AnimalLover(x))
C. (AnimalLover(a), Animal(b), Kills(a,b))
D. (Kills(Jack,Tuna), Kills(Curiosity,Tuna))
E. Cat(Tuna)
F. (Cat(z), Animal(z))
• Add the negation of query:
G: (Kills(Curiosity, Tuna))
28
• The resolution refutation proof
R1: G, D, {}
(Kills(Jack, Tuna))
R2: R1, C, {a/Jack, b/Tuna}
(~AnimalLover(Jack),
~Animal(Tuna))
R3: R2, B, {x/Jack}
(~Dog(y), ~Owns(Jack, y),
~Animal(Tuna))
R4: R3, A1, {y/D}
(~Owns(Jack, D),
~Animal(Tuna))
R5: R4, A2, {}
(~Animal(Tuna))
R6: R5, F, {z/Tuna}
(~Cat(Tuna))
R7: R6, E, {}
FALSE
29
• The proof tree
G
D
{}
R1: K(J,T)
C
{a/J,b/T}
R2: AL(J) A(T)
B
{x/J}
R3: D(y) O(J,y) A(T)
A1
{y/D}
R4: O(J,D), A(T)
A2
{}
R5: A(T)
F
{z/T}
R6: C(T)
A
{}
R7: FALSE
30
Decidability and Completeness
• Resolution is a refutation complete inference procedure for
First-Order Logic
– If a set of sentences contains a contradiction, then a
finite sequence of resolutions will prove this.
– If not, resolution may loop forever (“semi-decidable”)
• Here are notes by Charles Elkan that go into this more
deeply
31
Decidability and Completeness
• Refutation Completeness: If KB |= A then KB |- A
– If it’s entailed, then there’s a proof
• Semi-decidable:
– If there’s a proof, we’ll halt with it.
– If not, maybe halt, maybe not
• Logical entailment in FOL is semi-decidable: if the desired
conclusion follows from the premises, then eventually
resolution refutation will find a contradiction
32
Decidability and Completeness
• Propositional logic
– logical entailment is decidable
– There exists a complete inference procedure
• First-Order logic
– logical entailment is semi-decidable
– Resolution procedure is refutation complete
33
• Strategies (heuristics) for efficient
resolution include
– Unit preference. If a clause has only one
literal, use it first.
– Set of support. Identify “useful” rules and
ignore the rest. (p. 305)
– Input resolution. Intermediately generated
sentences can only be combined with original
inputs or original rules.
– Subsumption. Prune unnecessary facts from
the database.
34
Horn Clauses
• A Horn Clause is a CNF clause with at most one positive
literal
• Horn Clauses form the basis of forward and backward
chaining
• The Prolog language is based on Horn Clauses
• Deciding entailment with Horn Clauses is linear in the size of
the knowledge base
35
Reasoning with Horn Clauses
• Forward Chaining
– For each new piece of data, generate all new facts, until
the desired fact is generated
– Data-directed reasoning
• Backward Chaining
– To prove the goal, find a clause that contains the goal as
its head, and prove the body recursively
– Goal-directed reasoning
• The state space is an AND-OR graph; see 7.5.4
36
Forward Chaining over FO Definite (Horn)
Clauses
• Clauses (disjunctions) with at most one positive literal
• First-order literals can include variables, which are assumed
to be universally quantified
• Use GMP to perform forward chaining
(Semi-decidable as for full FOPC)
37
Def FOL-FC-Ask(KB,A) returns subst or false
KB: set of FO definite clauses with variables standardized apart
A: the query, an atomic sentence
Repeat until new is empty
new {}
for each implication (p1 ^ … ^ pn q) in KB:
for each T such that SUBST(T,p1^…^pn) =
SUBST(T,p1’^…^pn’) for some p1’,…,pn’ in KB
q’ SUBST(T,q)
if q’ is not a renaming of a sentence already in KB or new:
add q’ to new
S Unify(q’,A)
if S is not fail then return S
add new to KB
Return false
Process can be made more efficient; read on your own, for interest
38
Backward Chaining over Definite (Horn)
Clauses
• Logic programming
• Prolog is most popular form
• Depth-first search, so space requirements are lower, but
suffers from problems from repeated states
39
american(X) ^ weapon(Y) ^ sells(X,Y,Z) ^ hostile(Z) criminal(X).
owns(nono,m1). missile(m1).
missile(X1) ^ owns(nono,X1) sells(west,X1,nono).
missile(X2) weapon(X2).
enemy(X3,america) hostile(X3).
american(west).
enemy(nono,america).
Goal: criminal(west).
Backward chaining proof: in lecture
In Prolog:
criminal(X) :- american(X), weapon(Y), sells(X,Y,Z), hostile(Z).
40
Horn clauses are all of the form:
L1 ^ L2 ^ ... ^ Ln -> Ln+1
Or, equivalently, in clausal form:
~L1 v ~L2 v ... v ~Ln v Ln+1
Prolog (like databases) makes the "closed world assumption":
if P cannot be proved, infer not P
Think of the system as an arrogant know-it-all:
"If it were true, I would know it. Since I can't prove
it, it must not be true"
Thus, it uses "negation as failure".
41
neighbor(canada,us)
neighbor(mexico,us)
neighbor(pakistan,india)
?- neighbor(canada,india).
no
In full first-order logic, you would have to be able to
infer “~neighbor(canada,india)" for
"neighbor(canada,india)" to be false.
Be careful! “~neighbor(canada,india) is not entailed by the
Sentences above!
42
bachelor(X) :- male(X), \+ married(X).
male(bill).
male(jim).
married(bill).
married(mary).
An individual is a bachelor if it is male and it is
not married. \+ is the negation-as-failure operator in Prolog.
| ?- bachelor(bill).
no
| ?- bachelor(jim).
yes
| ?- bachelor(mary).
no
| ?- bachelor(X).
X = jim;
no
| ?43
Comparing backward chaining in
prolog with resolution
• [In lecture]
44
WrapUp
• You are responsible for everything in Chapter 9 except the
following (though you are encouraged to read them):
– Storage and Retrieval (p. starts bottom 328)
– Efficient forward chaining (starts p. 333) through
Irrelevant facts (ends top 337)
– Efficient implementation of logic programs (starts p.
340) through Constraint logic programming (ends p. 345)
– Completeness of resolution (starts p. 350) (though see
notes in slides)
• Also, see files posted on the schedule (clausal form
conversion, resolution, etc.)
45