Transcript Chapter 1
Social choice theory and
composite indicators:
In defense of linearity
Overview
Composite indicators vs MD social choice
Axioms & results for MD social choice
Implications for composite indicators
2
CI versus MD social choice
Illustration: we want to measure performance of
3 European countries (be,nl,lu)
1 benchmark country (us)
via 2 performance dimensions (only)
GDP/h: GDP per hour worked
SSR: Schooling Success Rate
3
CI versus MD social choice
SSR
: 2005
: 2006
nl
lu
us
be
Composite indicators allow us to compare
performance of countries, but not of groups of
GDP/h
countries ↔ MD social choice
allows both
4
Axioms for MD social choice
For simplicity we stick to the previous example
X x
be
x
nl
x
lu
x be
GDPh
be
x SSR
nl
x GDPh
x nlSSR
x luGDPh
x luSSR
assuming a fixed number of countries & equal population size
Purpose of MD social choice: find attractive rule to judge
whether one situation X is better or worse than another, say Y
But what is attractive? introduce axioms:
create simple imaginary situations X and Y in which it is (relatively) easy
to judge whether one situation is better than the other. All simple axioms
together leads to a rule (or a family of rules) which also allow(s) us to
judge more complex real-world situations
MD social choice axioms might also impose structure on CI’s
5
Three technical axioms
Completeness: either X is at least as good as Y, or Y is at least
as good as X (or both)
Transitivity: if X is at least as good as Y and Y is at least as
good as Z, then also X must be at least as good as Z
Continuity: (technical) small changes in a situation X cannot
lead to large changes in its comparison with other situations
Result 1 (Debreu, 1954)
If a rule satisfies Completeness, Transitivity as well as
Continuity then there exists a continuous function f s.t.
X is at least as good as Y if and only if f(X) ≥ f(Y).
6
Separability
Separability: countries with the same performance in two
situations X and Y do not matter when evaluating X and Y
SSR
: 2005
: 2006
Result 2 (Debreu, 1954; Blackorby, Donaldson
&
Auersperg, 1981; Tsui, 1995)
nl
If a rule satisfies
Separability
in addition to
lu
Completeness, Transitivity and Continuity then there
be
must exist continuous functions gbe, gnl and glu s.t.
X is at least as good as Y if and only if
gbe(xbe)+gnl(xnl)+glu(xlu) ≥ gbe(ybe)+gnl(ynl)+glu(ylu)
GDP/h
7
Monotonicity & Anonymity
Monotonicity: if all countries perform at least as good in X
compared to Y (& some better), then X is better than Y
Anonymity: the name of a country does not matter
Result 3
SSRIf a rule satisfies Monotonicity
SSR and Anonymity in
: 2005
: 2005
: 2006Completeness, Transitivity and
: 2006
addition to Separability,
nl
lu
Continuity
then there must exist a
lu
be
strictly
nl
increasing &
continuous
as
lu good as Y if
be function g s.t. X is at least be
and only if g(xbe)+g(xnl)+g(xlu) ≥ g(ybe)+g(ynl)+g(ylu)
g is the implicitGDP/h
CI-function of our rule which
GDP/h
measures the performance of countries!
8
Pigou-Dalton
Result
2006)
SSR 4 (Bosmans, Lauwers and Ooghe,: 2005
If a rule satisfies Pigou-Dalton in : 2006
addition to
Separability, Completeness, Transitivity, Continuous
Differentiability, Monotonicity
and Anonymity then
nl
lu
there exist weights
wGDPh,wSSR > 0 and a function h
with h’ > 0 and h” <be0 s.t. the CI-function g equals
g : xGDPh , xSSR hwGDPh xGDPh wSSR xSSR
GDP/h
9
Implications for CI’s
Perfect Substitutability between dimensions
SSR
: 2005
: 2006
nl
lu
be
GDP/h
10
Conclusion
Composite indicators vs MD social choice
If we want to be able to compare groups of countries
EU versus benchmark group
EU over time
Old EU versus new EU members
and if we care about convergence of countries,
then the implicit CI should be linear, i.e., a weighted sum of the
performance in the different dimensions.
11