Transcript EECS 690

EECS 690
January 27, 2010
Deontology
• Typically, when anyone talks about
Deontology, they mean to talk about
Immanuel Kant. Kant is THE deontologist.
• Deontology is an ethical framework that
holds that what makes an action right or
wrong is something that is contained in the
action itself, and not in its consequences.
• Deontology is the study of how to
determine what our moral duties are.
Rationality
• Kant regarded human rationality as a very
important consideration, and for several
reasons:
– Rationality is what separates us from the rest of the
animal world (following Aristotle here)
– If some action is to be right or wrong, anyone must be
able to determine which by means of reason (this
allows morality to apply universally among rational
beings)
– Rationality seems universally accepted as a measure
of both moral agency and moral subjecthood.
The Categorical Imperative
• The categorical imperative is Kant’s test to
see if an action can pass as moral.
• Kant phrased this test in between 3 and 5
different ways (depending on which Kant
scholar you ask)
• We will focus on two of these.
“The Kingdom of Sovereign Ends”
• Since reason is of supreme moral importance, it will be
immoral to treat rational beings as if they are not rational
beings.
• In Kant’s language, “So act that you use humanity,
whether in your own person or in the person of any
other, always at the same time as an end, never merely
as a means”
• In my language, “Don’t treat people like things. Ever.”
• Moral arguments that involve respect and dignity and
personal autonomy as inviolable moral principles have
the same intuition as Kant does here.
The Universal Law
• Kant: “Act only in accordance with that
maxim through which you can at the same
time will that it become a universal law”
• One thing that makes this principle work is
the idea that what is immoral for one
person should be immoral for all others.
• This principle is easily confused with the
“golden rule” but they are different.
Consider the following example:
Breaking promises
• If you’re considering breaking a promise,
consider what would happen if it were a
universal law for everyone to break their
promises.
• In such a case, promises don’t exist, so it is
rationally impossible to will that as a universal
law.
• If an action cannot be willed as a universal law,
then it is not moral. The idea is, “If it’s not okay
for everyone else to do it, why should it be okay
for me?”
Universality as a component of
morality
• This perspective is inspired by David Hume
• Many components of morality take the form of
widespread conventions. Promises can only
exist as the norm, and not an aberration.
• Respect for property, nonviolence, government,
law and order, etc. are all things that have to be
the norm to exist at all.
Similarities to Utilitarianism
• Utilitarianism and Kantianism will come to
the same verdict in almost all practical
cases, though the reasoning process is
very different. (see Johnson case study)
• Both theories are extremely demanding
Notable differences:
• Utilitarianism is a framework that tell you
what to do, Deontology is a framework that
mostly tells you what not to do.
• Deontology will come to a verdict on a
type of action, Utilitarianism will not.
(Deontology is inflexible, but consistent)
• Deontology does not consider
consequences, does not require
predictions.
Hybrid approaches
• James Moor, among others proposes that
Deontology will tell you what actions are
morally unacceptable, and utilitarianism
can select the best action from all the
permissible actions.
• Another approach uses the framework that
seems to best fit the given situation.